With great(er) power must come great(er) responsibility – An intercultural study of the social role effect on moral responsibility attribution

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Pascale Willemsen, Albert Newen, Karolina Prochownik, & Kaspar Kai
Willemsen, P., Newen, A., Prochownik, K., & Kai, K. (2023). With great(er) power must come great(er) responsibility – An intercultural study of the social role effect on moral responsibility attribution. Philosophical Psychology. https://doi-org.ezproxy.uzh.ch/10.1080/09515089.2023.2213277
Publication year: 2023

This paper investigates the relevance of social roles and hierarchies for the attribution of blame and causation in five culturally different countries, namely China, Germany, Poland, the United Arabic Emirates, and the United States of America. We demonstrate that in all these countries, hierarchical differences between the social roles occupied by two agents and associated differences in duties to care for others affect how these two agents are morally and causally judged when they make a decision together. Agents higher in a hierarchy are attributed more blame and considered more causally responsible for an action’s consequences. We also demonstrate that the degree of this effect depends on culture-specific differences in how hierarchies are conceived.

Tracing thick concepts through corpora

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Kevin Reuter, Lucien Baumgartner, & Pascale Willemsen
Reuter, K., Baumgartner, L., & Willemsen, P. (2023). Tracing thick and thin concepts through corpora. Language and Cognition, 1–20
Publication year: 2023

Philosophers and linguists currently lack the means to reliably identify evaluative concepts and measure their evaluative intensity. Using a corpus-based approach, we present a new method to distinguish evaluatively thick and thin adjectives like ‘courageous’ and ‘awful’ from descriptive adjectives like ‘narrow,’ and from value-associated adjectives like ‘sunny.’ Our study suggests that the modifiers ‘truly’ and ‘really’ frequently highlight the evaluative dimension of thick and thin adjectives, allowing for them to be uniquely classified. Based on these results, we believe our operationalization may pave the way for a more quantitative approach to the study of thick and thin concepts.

Pain Linguistics: A Case for Pluralism

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Sabrina Coninx, Pascale Willemsen, & Kevin Reuter
Coninx, S., Willemsen, P., & Reuter, K. (2023). Pain Linguistics: A Case for Pluralism. The Philosophical Quarterly, 74(1). https://doi.org/10.1093/pq/pqad048
Publication year: 2023

The most common approach to understanding the semantics of the concept of pain is third-person thought experiments. By contrast, the most frequent and most relevant uses of the folk concept of pain are from a first-person perspective in conversational settings. In this paper, we use a set of linguistic tools to systematically explore the semantics of what people communicate when reporting pain from a first-person perspective. Our results suggest that only a pluralistic view can do justice to the way we talk about pain from a first-person perspective: The semantic content of the folk concept of pain consists of information about both an unpleasant feeling and a disruptive bodily state. Pain linguistics thus provides new insights into ordinary pain language and poses an interesting challenge to the dominant unitary views of pain.

Mutual entailment between causation and responsibility

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Justin Sytsma, Pascale Willemsen, & Kevin Reuter
Sytsma, J., Willemsen, P. & Reuter, K. (2023). Mutual entailment between causation and responsibility. Philosophical Studies 180, 3593–3614. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-023-02041-2
Publication year: 2023

The standard view in philosophy is that responsibility entails causation. Most philosophers treat this entailment claim as an evident insight into the ordinary concepts of responsibility and causation. Further, it is taken to be equally obvious that the reversal of this claim does not hold: causation does not entail responsibility. In contrast, Sytsma and Livengood have put forward an account of the use of ordinary causal attributions (statements like “X caused Y”) that contends that they are typically used interchangeably with responsibility attributions (statements like “X is responsible for Y”). Put in terms of the concepts at play in these attributions, this account suggests that the reversal of the entailment claim may also hold, and, a fortiori, there would be mutual entailment between the ordinary concepts of responsibility and causation. Using the cancellability test, we report the results of three pre-registered studies providing empirical evidence that causation and responsibility are mutually entailed by each other.

Beyond the Courtroom: Agency and the Perception of Free will

Book ChapterPeer-reviewed
Machery, Edouard; Kneer, Markus; Willemsen, Pascale; Newen, Albert
Machery, E., Kneer, M. , Willemsen, P. , & Newen, A. (2023). Beyond the Courtroom: Agency and the Perception of Free Will. In P. Henne & S. Murray (Ed.). Advances in Experimental Philosophy of Action (pp. 171–189). London: Bloomsbury Academic. Retrieved January 9, 2024, from http://dx.doi.org/10.5040/9781350266353.0015
Publication year: 2023

In this paper, we call for a new approach to the psychology of free will attribution. While past research in experimental philosophy and psychology has mostly been focused on reasoning- based judgment (“the courtroom approach”), we argue that like agency and mindedness, free will can also be experienced perceptually (“the perceptual approach”). We further propose a new model of free will attribution—the agency model—according to which the experience of free will is elicited by the perceptual cues that prompt the attribution of agency. Finally, developing new stimuli that fit the perceptual approach, we present some preliminary evidence in support of the agency model.

The polarity effect of evaluative language

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Lucien Baumgartner, Pascale Willemsen, & Kevin Reuter
Baumgartner, L., Willemsen, P., & Reuter, K. (2022). The polarity effect of evaluative language. Philosophical Psychology. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2022.2123311
Publication year: 2022

Recent research on thick terms like “rude” and “friendly” has revealed a polarity effect, according to which the evaluative content of positive thick terms like “friendly” and “courageous” can be more easily canceled than the evaluative content of negative terms like “rude” and “selfish”. In this paper, we study the polarity effect in greater detail. We first demonstrate that the polarity effect is insensitive to manipulations of embeddings (Study 1). Second, we show that the effect occurs not only for thick terms but also for thin terms such as “good” or “bad” (Study 2). We conclude that the polarity effect indicates a pervasive asymmetry between positive and negative evaluative terms.

The polarity effect of evaluative language

Conference PaperPeer-reviewed
Lucien Baumgartner, Pascale Willemsen, & Kevin Reuter
Baumgartner, L., Willemsen, P., & Reuter, K. (2022). The polarity effect of evaluative language. In J. Culbertson, A. Perfors, Hugh Rabagliati, & V. Ramenzoni (Eds.), Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society. https://cognitivesciencesociety.org/wp-content/uploads/2022/07/CogSci2022Proceedings-1.pdf
Publication year: 2022

Recent research on thick terms like ‘rude’ and ‘friendly’ has revealed a polarity effect, according to which the evaluative content of positive thick terms like ‘friendly’ and ‘courageous’ can be more easily cancelled than the evaluative content of negative terms like ‘rude’ and ‘selfish’. In this paper, we study the polarity effect in greater detail. We first demonstrate that the polarity effect is insensitive to manipulations of embeddings (Study 1). Second, we show that the effect occurs not only for thick terms but also for thin terms such as ‘good’ or ‘bad’ (Study 2). We conclude that the polarity effect is indicative of a pervasive asymmetry that holds between positive and negative evaluative terms.

Separating the Evaluative from the Descriptive: An Empirical Study of Thick Concepts

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Pascale Willemsen, Kevin Reuter
Willemsen, P., & Reuter, K. (2021). Separating the Evaluative from the Descriptive: An Empirical Study of Thick Concepts. Thought. A Journal of Philosophy.
Publication year: 2021

Thick terms and concepts, such as honesty and cruelty, are at the heart of a variety of debates in philosophy of language and metaethics. Central to these debates is the question of how the descriptive and evaluative components of thick concepts are related and whether they can be separated from each other. So far, no empirical data on how thick terms are used in ordinary language has been collected to inform these debates. In this paper, we present the first empirical study, designed to investigate whether the evaluative component of thick concepts is communicated as part of the semantic meaning or by means of conversational implicatures. While neither the semantic nor the pragmatic view can fully account for the use of thick terms in ordinary language, our results do favor the semanticist interpretation: the evaluation of a thick concept is only slightly easier to cancel than semantically entailed content. We further discovered a polarity effect, demonstrating that how easily an evaluation can be cancelled depends on whether the thick term is of positive or negative polarity.

Lying, Deceptive Implicatures, and Commitment

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Alex Wiegmann, Pascale Willemsen, Joerg Meibauer
Wiegmann, A., Willemsen, P., & Meibauer, J. (2022). Lying, Deceptive Implicatures, and Commitment. Ergo (Ann Arbor, Mich.), 8. https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.2251
Publication year: 2021

Deceptive implicatures are a subtle communicative device for leading someone into a false belief. However, it is widely accepted that deceiving by means of deceptive implicature does not amount to lying. In this paper, we put this claim to the empirical test and present evidence that the traditional definition of lying might be too narrow to capture the folk concept of lying. Four hundred participants were presented with fourteen vignettes containing utterances that communicate conversational implicatures which the speaker believes to be false. We further collected several potential proxy measures of lying, to get a better understanding of when a deceptive implicature is considered a case of lying. The results indicate that most implicatures (ten out of fourteen) were evaluated as lies and that lie ratings were closely tracked by the degree to which speakers were considered to have committed themselves to the truth of the content conveyed by their deceptive implicatures.

Direct and Derivative Moral Responsibility. An Overlooked Distinction in Experimental Philosophy

Book ChapterPeer-reviewed
Pascale Willemsen
Willemsen, P. (2022). Direct and Derivative Moral Responsibility: An Overlooked Distinction in Experimental Philosophy. In T. Nadelhoffer & A. Monroe (Ed.). Advances in Experimental Philosophy of Free Will and Responsibility (pp. 143–166). London,: Bloomsbury Academic. http://dx.doi.org/10.5040/9781350188112.ch-008
Publication year: 2021

Moral philosophers draw an important distinction between two kinds of moral responsibility. An agent can be directly morally responsible, or they can be derivatively morally responsible. Many scholars in the debate believe that direct moral responsibility for an action presupposes that the agent could have acted other than she actually did. However, in some situations, we hold agents responsible even though they could not have acted differently, such as when they recklessly cause an accident or do not take adequate precautions to avoid harmful consequences. Moral philosophers often argue that what we ascribe in these cases is derivative moral responsibility for the action, which results from direct moral responsibility for some other, earlier action. In this paper, I apply this conceptual distinction to the experimental debate about so-called folk-compatibilism or, more precisely, to the question of whether the folk reject the Principle of Alternative Possibilities. I argue that experimental philosophers have failed to consider this distinction when designing experiments and interpreting their results. With the help of three experiments, I demonstrate that intuitions which seem to conflict with the Principle of Alternative Possibilities are best explained by the attribution of derivative moral responsibility. For this reason, these studies do not speak in favour of compatibilism.

Can a Question Be a Lie? An Empirical Investigation

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Emanuel Viebahn, Alex Wiegmann, Neele Engelmann, Pascale Willemsen
Viebahn, E. & Wiegmann, A. & Engelmann, N. & Willemsen, P., (2021) “Can a Question Be a Lie? An Empirical Investigation”, Ergo an Open Access Journal of Philosophy 8: 7. doi: https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.1144
Publication year: 2021

In several recent papers and a monograph, Andreas Stokke argues that questions can be misleading, but that they cannot be lies. The aim of this paper is to show that ordinary speakers disagree. We show that ordinary speakers judge certain kinds of insincere questions to be lies, namely questions carrying a believed- false presupposition the speaker intends to convey. These judgements are robust and remain so when the participants are given the possibility of classifying the utterances as misleading or as deceiving. The judgements contrast with judgements participants give about cases of misleading or deceptive behaviour, and they pattern with judgements participants make about declarative lies. Finally, the possibility of lying with non-declaratives is not confined to questions: ordinary speakers also judge utterances of imperative, exclamative and optative sentences carrying believed-false presuppositions to be lies.

The Relevance of Alternate Possibilities for Moral Responsibility for Actions and Omissions

Book ChapterPeer-reviewed
Pascale Willemsen
Willemsen, P. (2020). The Relevance of Alternate Possibilities for Moral Responsibility for Actions and Omissions. In T. Lombrozo, J. Knobe, and S. Nichols (Eds.), Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy (Vol. 3). DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198852407.003.0011
Publication year: 2020

In this paper, I present three original, pre-registered experiments that test the relevance of alternative possibilities for the attribution of moral responsibility. Many philosophers have argued that alternative possibilities are required for an agent’s moral responsibility for the consequences of omitting an action. In contrast, it is argued that alternative possibilities are not required for moral responsibility for the consequences of performing an action. Thus, while an agent can be morally responsible for an action she could not have avoided, an agent is never morally responsible for omitting an action she could not have performed. Call this the Action/Omission Asymmetry Thesis. In this paper, I discuss various strategies to challenge the Action/Omission Asymmetry Thesis. I identify the predictions those strategies make about the conditions under which an agent will be held morally responsible for an unavoidable action or omission. These predictions are subsequently tested in three experiments to evaluate their respective plausibility. I demonstrate that whether there is an Action/Omission Asymmetry strongly depends, first, on the type of moral judgment we consider relevant for the Action/Omission Asymmetry Thesis, and, second, the scale we use to test the folk’s intuitions.

Separability and the Effect of Valence An Empirical Study of Thick Concepts

Conference PaperPeer-reviewed
Pascale Willemsen, Kevin Reuter
Willemsen, P., & Reuter, K. (2020). Separability and the Effect of Valence. Proceedings of the 42th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society 2020, pp. 794-800.
Publication year: 2020

Thick terms and concepts, such as honesty and cruelty, are at the heart of a variety of debates in linguistics, philosophy of language, and metaethics. Central to these debates is the question of how the descriptive and evaluative components of thick concepts are related and whether they can be separated from each other. So far, no empirical data on how thick terms are used in ordinary language has been collected to inform these debates. In this paper, we present the first empirical study, designed to investigate whether the evaluative component of thick concepts can be separated. Our study might be considered to support the view that separation is not possible. However, our study also reveals an effect of valence, indicating that people reason differently about positive and negative thick terms. While evaluations cannot be cancelled for negative thick terms, they can be for positive ones. Three follow-up studies were conducted to explain this effect. We conclude that the effect of valence is best accounted for by a difference in the social norms guiding evaluative language.

Omissions and Their Moral Relevance. Assessing causal and moral responsibility for the things we fail to do

BookPeer-reviewed
Pascale Willemsen
Willemsen, P. (2019). Omissions and their moral relevance. Brill | mentis. https://doi.org/10.30965/9783957437952
Publication year: 2019

This book empirically investigates the social practice of ascribing moral responsibility to others for the things they failed to do, and it discusses the philosophical relevance of this practice. In our everyday life, we often blame others for things they failed to do. For instance, we might blame our neighbour for not watering our plants during our vacation. Interestingly, the attribution of blame is typically accompanied by the attribution of causal responsibility. We do not only blame our neighbour for not watering our plants, but we do so because we believe that not watering the plants caused them to dry up and die. In this book, I investigate how we make moral and causal judgments about omissions. I discuss different philosophical perspectives on this matter, and I outline to what extent the actual social practice is in line with philosophical theories.

Causal attribution and corpus analysis

Book ChapterPeer-reviewed
Justin Sytsma, Roland Bluhm, Pascale Willemsen, Kevin Reuter
Sytsma, J., Bluhm, R., Willemsen, P., & Reuter, K. (2019). Causal Attributions and Corpus Analysis. In E. Fischer & M. Curtis (Ed.). Methodological Advances in Experimental Philosophy (pp. 209–238). London, Bloomsbury Academic
Publication year: 2019

Although philosophers have often held that causation is a purely descriptive notion, a growing body of experimental work on ordinary causal attributions using questionnaire methods indicates that it is heavily influenced by normative information. These results have been the subject of sceptical challenges. Additionally, those who find the results compelling have disagreed about how best to explain them. In this chapter, we help resolve these debates by using a new set of tools to investigate ordinary causal attributions—the methods of corpus linguistics. We apply both more qualitative corpus analysis techniques and the more purely quantitative methods of distributional semantics to four target questions: (a) Can corpus analysis provide independent support for the thesis that ordinary causal attributions are sensitive to normative information? (b) Does the evidence coming from corpus analysis support the contention that outcome valence matters for ordinary causal attributions? (c) Are ordinary causal attributions similar to responsibility attributions? (d) Are causal attributions of philosophers different from causal attributions we find in corpora of more ordinary language? We argue that the results of our analyses support a positive answer to each of these questions.

Recent empirical work on the relationship between causal judgements and norms

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Pascale Willemsen, Lara Kirfel
Willemsen, P., & Kirfel, L. (2018). Recent empirical work on the relationship between causal judgements and norms. Philosophy Compass, https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12562
Publication year: 2018

It has recently been argued that normative considerations play an important role in causal cognition. For instance, when an agent violates a moral rule and thereby produces a negative outcome, she will be judged to be much more of a cause of the outcome, compared to someone who performed the same action but did not violate a norm. While there is a substantial amount of evidence reporting these effects, it is still a matter of debate how this evidence is to be interpreted. In this paper, we engage with the three most influential classes of explanations, namely, (a) the Norm‐Sensitive Cognitive Process View, (b) the Normative Concept View, and (c) the Pragmatics View. We will outline how these theories explain the empirical results and in what ways they differ. We conclude with a reflection on how well these strategies do overall and what questions they still leave unanswered.

Omissions and Expectations: A New Approach to the Things We Failed to Do

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Pascale Willemsen
Willemsen, P. (2018). Omissions and expectations: a new approach to the things we failed to do. Synthese 195, 1587–1614. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1284-9
Publication year: 2018

Imagine you and your friend Pierre agreed on meeting each other at a café, but he does not show up. What is the difference between a friend’s not showing up at your meeting and any other person not coming? In some sense, all people who did not come show the same kind of behaviour, but most people would be willing to say that the absence of a friend who you expected to see is different in kind. In this paper, I will spell out this difference by investigating laypeople’s conceptualisation of absences of actions in four experiments. In languages such as German, French, Italian, or Polish, people consider a friend’s not coming an omission. Any other person’s not coming, in contrast, is not considered an omission at all, but just a mere nothing. This use of the term omission differs from the usage in English, where ‘omission’ refers to all kinds of absences. In addition, ‘omission’ is not even an everyday term, but invented by philosophers for the sake of philosophical investigation. In other languages, ‘omission’ (and its synonyms) is part of an everyday vocabulary. Finally, I will discuss how this folk concept of omission could be made fruitful for philosophical questions.

A new look at the attribution of moral responsibility: The underestimated relevance of social roles

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Pascale Willemsen, Albert Newen, Kai Kaspar
Willemsen, P., Newen, A., & Kai, K. (2018). A new look at the attribution of moral responsibility: The underestimated relevance of social roles, Philosophical Psychology, 31:4, 595-608, DOI: 10.1080/09515089.2018.1429592
Publication year: 2018

What are the main features that influence our attribution of moral responsibility? It is widely accepted that there are various factors which strongly influence our moral judgments, such as the agent’s intentions, the consequences of the action, the causal involvement of the agent, and the agent’s freedom and ability to do otherwise. In this paper, we argue that this picture is incomplete: We argue that social roles are an additional key factor that is radically underestimated in the extant literature. We will present an experiment to support this claim.

Marbles in inaction: Counterfactual simulation and causation by omissions

Conference PaperPeer-reviewed
Simon Stephan, Pascale Willemsen, Tobias Gerstenberg
Stephan, S., Willemsen, P., & Gerstenberg, T (2017). Marbles in inaction: Counterfactual simulation and causation by omissions. Proceedings of the 35th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society 2017, pp. 1132-1137
Publication year: 2017

Consider the following causal explanation: The ball went through the goal because the defender didn’t block it. There are at least two problems with citing omissions as causal explanations. First, how do we choose the relevant candidate omission (e.g. why the defender and not the goalkeeper). Second, how do we determine what would have happened in the relevant counterfactual situation (i.e. maybe the shot would still have gone through the goal even if it had been blocked). In this paper, we extend the counterfactual simulation model (CSM) of causal judgment (Gerstenberg, Goodman, Lagnado, & Tenenbaum, 2014) to handle the second problem. In two experiments, we show how people’s causal model of the situation affects their causal judgments via influencing what counterfactuals they consider. Omissions are considered causes to the extent that the outcome in the relevant counterfactual situation would have been different from what it actually was.

How the truth can make a great lie: An empirical investigation of lying by falsely implicating

Conference PaperPeer-reviewed
Alex Wiegmann, Pascale Willemsen
Wiegmann, A., & Willemsen, P. (2017). How the truth can make a great lie : an empirical investigation of the folk concept of lying by falsely implicating. Cognitive Science Society. https://doi.org/10.5167/uzh-175885
Publication year: 2017

Is it possible to lie despite not saying anyhing false? While the spontaneous answer seems to be ‘no’, there is some evidence from ordinary language that a lie does not require what is said to be believed-false. In this paper, we will argue for a pragmatic extension of the standard definition of lying. More specifically, we will present three experiments which show that people’s concept of lying is not about what is said, but about what is implied by saying it that way. We test three Gricean conversational maxims. For each one of them we demonstrate that if a speaker implies something misleading, even by saying something semantically true, it is still considered lying.

Empirically investigating the concept of lying

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Alex Wiegmann, Ronja Rutschmann, Pascale Willemsen
Wiegmann, A., Rutschmann, R. & Willemsen, P. (2017). Empirically Investigating the Concept of Lying. Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 34, 591–609. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-017-0112-z
Publication year: 2017

Lying is an everyday moral phenomenon about which philosophers have written a lot. Not only the moral status of lying has been intensively discussed but also what it means to lie in the first place. Perhaps the most important criterion for an adequate definition of lying is that it fits with people’s understanding and use of this concept. In this light, it comes as a surprise that researchers only recently started to empirically investigate the folk concept of lying. In this paper, we describe three experimental studies which address the following questions: Does a statement need to be objectively false in order to constitute lying? Does lying necessarily include the intention to deceive? Can one lie by omitting relevant facts?

Is there really an omission effect?

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Pascale Willemsen, Kevin Reuter
Willemsen, P., & Reuter, K. (2016). Is there really an omission effect? Philosophical Psychology, 29(8), 1142–1159. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2016.1225194
Publication year: 2016

The omission effect, first described by Spranca and colleagues (Spranca, Minsk, & Baron, 1991), has since been extensively studied and repeatedly confirmed (Cushman, Murray, Gordon-McKeon, Wharton, & Greene, 2012). All else being equal, most people judge it to be morally worse to actively bring about a negative event than to passively allow that event to happen. In this paper, we provide new experimental data that challenges previous studies of the omission effect both methodologically and philosophically. We argue that previous studies have failed to control for the equivalence of rules that are violated by actions and omissions. Once equivalent norms are introduced, our results show that the omission effect is eliminated, even if the negative outcome of the behavior is foreseen and intended by the agent. We show that the omission effect does not constitute a basic, moral disposition but occurs exclusively in complex moral situations. Building on these empirical results, we cast doubt onto two influential explanations of the omission effect, the Causal Relevance Hypothesis and the Overgeneralization Hypothesis, and provide a novel explanation of the phenomenon. Furthermore, we discuss various ramifications of the interplay between our understanding of omissions and legal systems.