With great(er) power must come great(er) responsibility – An intercultural study of the social role effect on moral responsibility attribution

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Pascale Willemsen, Albert Newen, Karolina Prochownik, & Kaspar Kai
Willemsen, P., Newen, A., Prochownik, K., & Kai, K. (2023). With great(er) power must come great(er) responsibility – An intercultural study of the social role effect on moral responsibility attribution. Philosophical Psychology. https://doi-org.ezproxy.uzh.ch/10.1080/09515089.2023.2213277
Publication year: 2023

This paper investigates the relevance of social roles and hierarchies for the attribution of blame and causation in five culturally different countries, namely China, Germany, Poland, the United Arabic Emirates, and the United States of America. We demonstrate that in all these countries, hierarchical differences between the social roles occupied by two agents and associated differences in duties to care for others affect how these two agents are morally and causally judged when they make a decision together. Agents higher in a hierarchy are attributed more blame and considered more causally responsible for an action’s consequences. We also demonstrate that the degree of this effect depends on culture-specific differences in how hierarchies are conceived.

Tracing thick concepts through corpora

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Kevin Reuter, Lucien Baumgartner, & Pascale Willemsen
Reuter, K., Baumgartner, L., & Willemsen, P. (2023). Tracing thick and thin concepts through corpora. Language and Cognition, 1–20
Publication year: 2023

Philosophers and linguists currently lack the means to reliably identify evaluative concepts and measure their evaluative intensity. Using a corpus-based approach, we present a new method to distinguish evaluatively thick and thin adjectives like ‘courageous’ and ‘awful’ from descriptive adjectives like ‘narrow,’ and from value-associated adjectives like ‘sunny.’ Our study suggests that the modifiers ‘truly’ and ‘really’ frequently highlight the evaluative dimension of thick and thin adjectives, allowing for them to be uniquely classified. Based on these results, we believe our operationalization may pave the way for a more quantitative approach to the study of thick and thin concepts.

Pain Linguistics: A Case for Pluralism

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Sabrina Coninx, Pascale Willemsen, & Kevin Reuter
Coninx, S., Willemsen, P., & Reuter, K. (2023). Pain Linguistics: A Case for Pluralism. The Philosophical Quarterly, 74(1). https://doi.org/10.1093/pq/pqad048
Publication year: 2023

The most common approach to understanding the semantics of the concept of pain is third-person thought experiments. By contrast, the most frequent and most relevant uses of the folk concept of pain are from a first-person perspective in conversational settings. In this paper, we use a set of linguistic tools to systematically explore the semantics of what people communicate when reporting pain from a first-person perspective. Our results suggest that only a pluralistic view can do justice to the way we talk about pain from a first-person perspective: The semantic content of the folk concept of pain consists of information about both an unpleasant feeling and a disruptive bodily state. Pain linguistics thus provides new insights into ordinary pain language and poses an interesting challenge to the dominant unitary views of pain.

Mutual entailment between causation and responsibility

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Justin Sytsma, Pascale Willemsen, & Kevin Reuter
Sytsma, J., Willemsen, P. & Reuter, K. (2023). Mutual entailment between causation and responsibility. Philosophical Studies 180, 3593–3614. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-023-02041-2
Publication year: 2023

The standard view in philosophy is that responsibility entails causation. Most philosophers treat this entailment claim as an evident insight into the ordinary concepts of responsibility and causation. Further, it is taken to be equally obvious that the reversal of this claim does not hold: causation does not entail responsibility. In contrast, Sytsma and Livengood have put forward an account of the use of ordinary causal attributions (statements like “X caused Y”) that contends that they are typically used interchangeably with responsibility attributions (statements like “X is responsible for Y”). Put in terms of the concepts at play in these attributions, this account suggests that the reversal of the entailment claim may also hold, and, a fortiori, there would be mutual entailment between the ordinary concepts of responsibility and causation. Using the cancellability test, we report the results of three pre-registered studies providing empirical evidence that causation and responsibility are mutually entailed by each other.

The polarity effect of evaluative language

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Lucien Baumgartner, Pascale Willemsen, & Kevin Reuter
Baumgartner, L., Willemsen, P., & Reuter, K. (2022). The polarity effect of evaluative language. Philosophical Psychology. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2022.2123311
Publication year: 2022

Recent research on thick terms like “rude” and “friendly” has revealed a polarity effect, according to which the evaluative content of positive thick terms like “friendly” and “courageous” can be more easily canceled than the evaluative content of negative terms like “rude” and “selfish”. In this paper, we study the polarity effect in greater detail. We first demonstrate that the polarity effect is insensitive to manipulations of embeddings (Study 1). Second, we show that the effect occurs not only for thick terms but also for thin terms such as “good” or “bad” (Study 2). We conclude that the polarity effect indicates a pervasive asymmetry between positive and negative evaluative terms.

Separating the Evaluative from the Descriptive: An Empirical Study of Thick Concepts

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Pascale Willemsen, Kevin Reuter
Willemsen, P., & Reuter, K. (2021). Separating the Evaluative from the Descriptive: An Empirical Study of Thick Concepts. Thought. A Journal of Philosophy.
Publication year: 2021

Thick terms and concepts, such as honesty and cruelty, are at the heart of a variety of debates in philosophy of language and metaethics. Central to these debates is the question of how the descriptive and evaluative components of thick concepts are related and whether they can be separated from each other. So far, no empirical data on how thick terms are used in ordinary language has been collected to inform these debates. In this paper, we present the first empirical study, designed to investigate whether the evaluative component of thick concepts is communicated as part of the semantic meaning or by means of conversational implicatures. While neither the semantic nor the pragmatic view can fully account for the use of thick terms in ordinary language, our results do favor the semanticist interpretation: the evaluation of a thick concept is only slightly easier to cancel than semantically entailed content. We further discovered a polarity effect, demonstrating that how easily an evaluation can be cancelled depends on whether the thick term is of positive or negative polarity.

Lying, Deceptive Implicatures, and Commitment

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Alex Wiegmann, Pascale Willemsen, Joerg Meibauer
Wiegmann, A., Willemsen, P., & Meibauer, J. (2022). Lying, Deceptive Implicatures, and Commitment. Ergo (Ann Arbor, Mich.), 8. https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.2251
Publication year: 2021

Deceptive implicatures are a subtle communicative device for leading someone into a false belief. However, it is widely accepted that deceiving by means of deceptive implicature does not amount to lying. In this paper, we put this claim to the empirical test and present evidence that the traditional definition of lying might be too narrow to capture the folk concept of lying. Four hundred participants were presented with fourteen vignettes containing utterances that communicate conversational implicatures which the speaker believes to be false. We further collected several potential proxy measures of lying, to get a better understanding of when a deceptive implicature is considered a case of lying. The results indicate that most implicatures (ten out of fourteen) were evaluated as lies and that lie ratings were closely tracked by the degree to which speakers were considered to have committed themselves to the truth of the content conveyed by their deceptive implicatures.

Can a Question Be a Lie? An Empirical Investigation

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Emanuel Viebahn, Alex Wiegmann, Neele Engelmann, Pascale Willemsen
Viebahn, E. & Wiegmann, A. & Engelmann, N. & Willemsen, P., (2021) “Can a Question Be a Lie? An Empirical Investigation”, Ergo an Open Access Journal of Philosophy 8: 7. doi: https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.1144
Publication year: 2021

In several recent papers and a monograph, Andreas Stokke argues that questions can be misleading, but that they cannot be lies. The aim of this paper is to show that ordinary speakers disagree. We show that ordinary speakers judge certain kinds of insincere questions to be lies, namely questions carrying a believed- false presupposition the speaker intends to convey. These judgements are robust and remain so when the participants are given the possibility of classifying the utterances as misleading or as deceiving. The judgements contrast with judgements participants give about cases of misleading or deceptive behaviour, and they pattern with judgements participants make about declarative lies. Finally, the possibility of lying with non-declaratives is not confined to questions: ordinary speakers also judge utterances of imperative, exclamative and optative sentences carrying believed-false presuppositions to be lies.

Recent empirical work on the relationship between causal judgements and norms

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Pascale Willemsen, Lara Kirfel
Willemsen, P., & Kirfel, L. (2018). Recent empirical work on the relationship between causal judgements and norms. Philosophy Compass, https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12562
Publication year: 2018

It has recently been argued that normative considerations play an important role in causal cognition. For instance, when an agent violates a moral rule and thereby produces a negative outcome, she will be judged to be much more of a cause of the outcome, compared to someone who performed the same action but did not violate a norm. While there is a substantial amount of evidence reporting these effects, it is still a matter of debate how this evidence is to be interpreted. In this paper, we engage with the three most influential classes of explanations, namely, (a) the Norm‐Sensitive Cognitive Process View, (b) the Normative Concept View, and (c) the Pragmatics View. We will outline how these theories explain the empirical results and in what ways they differ. We conclude with a reflection on how well these strategies do overall and what questions they still leave unanswered.

Omissions and Expectations: A New Approach to the Things We Failed to Do

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Pascale Willemsen
Willemsen, P. (2018). Omissions and expectations: a new approach to the things we failed to do. Synthese 195, 1587–1614. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1284-9
Publication year: 2018

Imagine you and your friend Pierre agreed on meeting each other at a café, but he does not show up. What is the difference between a friend’s not showing up at your meeting and any other person not coming? In some sense, all people who did not come show the same kind of behaviour, but most people would be willing to say that the absence of a friend who you expected to see is different in kind. In this paper, I will spell out this difference by investigating laypeople’s conceptualisation of absences of actions in four experiments. In languages such as German, French, Italian, or Polish, people consider a friend’s not coming an omission. Any other person’s not coming, in contrast, is not considered an omission at all, but just a mere nothing. This use of the term omission differs from the usage in English, where ‘omission’ refers to all kinds of absences. In addition, ‘omission’ is not even an everyday term, but invented by philosophers for the sake of philosophical investigation. In other languages, ‘omission’ (and its synonyms) is part of an everyday vocabulary. Finally, I will discuss how this folk concept of omission could be made fruitful for philosophical questions.

A new look at the attribution of moral responsibility: The underestimated relevance of social roles

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Pascale Willemsen, Albert Newen, Kai Kaspar
Willemsen, P., Newen, A., & Kai, K. (2018). A new look at the attribution of moral responsibility: The underestimated relevance of social roles, Philosophical Psychology, 31:4, 595-608, DOI: 10.1080/09515089.2018.1429592
Publication year: 2018

What are the main features that influence our attribution of moral responsibility? It is widely accepted that there are various factors which strongly influence our moral judgments, such as the agent’s intentions, the consequences of the action, the causal involvement of the agent, and the agent’s freedom and ability to do otherwise. In this paper, we argue that this picture is incomplete: We argue that social roles are an additional key factor that is radically underestimated in the extant literature. We will present an experiment to support this claim.

Empirically investigating the concept of lying

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Alex Wiegmann, Ronja Rutschmann, Pascale Willemsen
Wiegmann, A., Rutschmann, R. & Willemsen, P. (2017). Empirically Investigating the Concept of Lying. Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 34, 591–609. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-017-0112-z
Publication year: 2017

Lying is an everyday moral phenomenon about which philosophers have written a lot. Not only the moral status of lying has been intensively discussed but also what it means to lie in the first place. Perhaps the most important criterion for an adequate definition of lying is that it fits with people’s understanding and use of this concept. In this light, it comes as a surprise that researchers only recently started to empirically investigate the folk concept of lying. In this paper, we describe three experimental studies which address the following questions: Does a statement need to be objectively false in order to constitute lying? Does lying necessarily include the intention to deceive? Can one lie by omitting relevant facts?

Is there really an omission effect?

Journal PaperPeer-reviewed
Pascale Willemsen, Kevin Reuter
Willemsen, P., & Reuter, K. (2016). Is there really an omission effect? Philosophical Psychology, 29(8), 1142–1159. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2016.1225194
Publication year: 2016

The omission effect, first described by Spranca and colleagues (Spranca, Minsk, & Baron, 1991), has since been extensively studied and repeatedly confirmed (Cushman, Murray, Gordon-McKeon, Wharton, & Greene, 2012). All else being equal, most people judge it to be morally worse to actively bring about a negative event than to passively allow that event to happen. In this paper, we provide new experimental data that challenges previous studies of the omission effect both methodologically and philosophically. We argue that previous studies have failed to control for the equivalence of rules that are violated by actions and omissions. Once equivalent norms are introduced, our results show that the omission effect is eliminated, even if the negative outcome of the behavior is foreseen and intended by the agent. We show that the omission effect does not constitute a basic, moral disposition but occurs exclusively in complex moral situations. Building on these empirical results, we cast doubt onto two influential explanations of the omission effect, the Causal Relevance Hypothesis and the Overgeneralization Hypothesis, and provide a novel explanation of the phenomenon. Furthermore, we discuss various ramifications of the interplay between our understanding of omissions and legal systems.